|
William
Harrison was a prominent Elizabethan intellectual, best known for
his Description of Britain, included in the second edition
of Holinsheds Chronicles
(1587). He was also the author of a Chronology of world
history outlining the apocalyptic battle between the true, spiritual
Protestant Church and the corrupt, worldly Catholic Church. Histories
of such figures can be dry and dutiful affairs that only warrant
the fleeting attention of the dedicated specialist. However, Dr
Parrys rigorous and historically engaged analysis of the writings
of his subject and his ability to contextualise Harrisons
work within the Protestant culture of late Elizabethan England,
distinguishes his monograph from run-of-the-mill studies and Cambridge
are to be congratulated for reprinting this work fifteen years after
its publication. A Protestant Vision
demands to be read, even if one is not specifically interested in
Harrison or in the progress of the English Reformation after John
Bale. Parry shows how any account of Tudor intellectual culture
must take into account the close relationship between religion,
politics and historical writing, indicating that emphasising any
one at the expense of the others will result in a distorted and
partial picture.
A Protestant
Vision consists of seven lengthy chapters and is divided
into two parts, the first dealing with Harrisons view of history,
the second with his vision of England. Chapter one, The Two
Churches, shows how the enthusiastic young Protestant convert
came to feel that if history was studied closely and scrupulously
enough he would be able to establish a means of judging the successes
and failures of the Elizabethan Church as part of the prophetic
continuum of history (p. 9). In this way Harrison was following
in the footsteps of John Bale, who read the Revelation
as a direct historical allegory of the progress of the evil Catholic
Church and the saintly but persecuted True Church, which had only
just been able to re-establish itself after centuries of domination
of the kingdoms of darkness. The implication was that Satanic elements
were still lurking within the church: the problem was to identify
exactly what they were.
Harrison was confident of his ability to
achieve this monumental task. After all, his religion granted him
an unchanging godly insight that could resurrect
the full experience of the earliest moments of time (p. 20),
ideal qualities for a historian. Historical analysis was also made
straightforward by the continuum assumed here whereby the
past and present had the same meaning (p. 29), as history
moved towards its final goal of Christs return. On the one
hand, Harrisons faith made him optimistic that everything
pointed in the same direction and he could afford to ignore messy
or stubbornly inconvenient evidence. On the other, his sense of
the inadequacies of Elizabeths church settlement and the compromises
that she was prepared to make to preserve her position and protect
the legacy of the Reformation, led to a certain amount of frustration
and despair.
Chapters two and three provide a careful
analysis of Harrisons Chronology, a work which
attempted to elaborate the nature and design of Gods will
alongside the foolish and catastrophic errors of human society attempting
to implement or thwart their maker. Harrison remained within
the mainstream of apocalyptic interpretation which had been popularised
in England by Bale (p. 70). Rome had become generally known
as the second Babylon by 961 AD, and Satan had been loosed into
the world by 1001 AD. When the Lateran decree of 1215 gave the papacy
power over secular rulers, Harrison argued that Satan had truly
begun to dominate the world until properly resisted by the forces
of the Reformation. Mainstream such interpretation may have been
but Harrison was independent enough to take issue with the well-known
view of John Foxe that the number of the beast, 666, referred to
a specific year. Harrison, rather more sensibly, argued that the
number signified a measuring rod (p. 72) which would
reveal how bad any particular event or action might be. Dr Parry
also points out that Harrison made extensive use of Jean Bodins
Methodis ad Facilem Historiarum Cognitionem
(first published in 1566) to expound theories of numerology and
cosmic significance. That Harrison was able to ignore Bodins
absolutist political theories, conceived in the wake of the bloody
French wars of religion and formulated in direct opposition to the
Huguenot monarchomach writings which clearly did influence Harrisons
thought, further indicates that Harrison was capable of ploughing
his own furrow. Dr Parry makes this point but perhaps does not fully
emphasise its importance.
The second section shows how Harrison applied
his ideas to the state of Elizabethan England in his published work.
Chapter four explains how he envisaged his ideal church, beliefs
which marked Harrison out as a puritan within the church who felt
that reforms had not gone far enough. In general Harrison was less
content to accept that much church practice fell under the heading
of things indifferent than more moderate Protestants
and he was keen to purge the church of grievous errors and other
popish trash. He felt that any remaining elements of
the Church of Cain should be scrupulously removed and took a hard
line on the vestments controversy, arguing that plain garments that
did not separate pastor and flock too drastically were best fitted
for worship in Gods house. Nevertheless, Harrison was enough
of a pragmatist to accept that opposition to Rome could not be built
in a day and he accepted the use of the surplice in the short term.
He was also prepared to tolerate the existence of bishops, although
he clearly would have preferred to see the church less hierarchically
governed (Dr Parry suggests that Harrison was confused and uncertain
about this point, but is it not more likely that he felt the need
not to isolate himself from the mainstream by arguing too idealistically
and aggressively?). Harrison enthusiastically endorsed rites such
as churching, believing that it was the duty of good Christians
to multiply and so increase Gods kingdom, whatever false emphasis
might be placed on the holy nature of virginity as a Satanic trick
to fool the devout. Overall, Harrison placed greatest emphasis on
the word rather than the institution, a familiar enough Protestant
preference.
Probably the most interesting chapters in
the book are 5 and 6 which deal with Harrisons blueprint for
a reformed prince and a reformed commonwealth. Although Harrison
placed great emphasis on the law of nature in his discussions of
numerology and prophecy chapter 7 outlines his interest in
Hermetic philosophy he made a distinct separation between
the natural world and the human world of politics and its institutions.
Revelation was the key and such direct insight into the mind of
God enabled the true believer to disregard ordinary observations
and rules. Harrisons sense of value links him to Thomas More,
a thinker he resembles, even though many of the Protestant philosophers
and polemicists who influenced Harrison tried their hardest to dismiss
More as a false martyr obsessed with worldly rather than spiritual
gain. Like More, Harrison seems to have feared compromise less than
isolation in his attempts to argue for reform, and he also clearly
felt that Christian revelation could and should override more mundane
perspectives of the world.
However, this Christian rejection of the
natural world paradoxically secularises political thought, or, at
least, opens the way for a clear separation between politics and
religion. The point that Dr Parry carefully makes is that admitting
that human values and means of interpretation can determine political
behaviour, rather than the natural world, means that political discussions
do not have to be determined by religion alone. Rational argument
can take place as a means of settling religious disputes about politics.
As Quentin Skinner observed, the godly necessity of revolution
did not bind Calvinists to specifically Calvinist arguments
(p. 209) but enabled them to advance defences of their actions based
on arguments derived from natural law theorists. Political behaviour
could be separated from what the Scriptures revealed as essential
for revelation (p. 211). While John Ponet and Christopher
Goodman, English Calvinists writing during the reign of Mary Tudor,
had claimed that true believers should resist and overthrow the
queen because of her hostility to Protestantism, Harrison had to
make the rather less spectacular argument that he might be able
to influence Elizabeth through the use of religious argument and
turn her back to the true path. This is the central reason, one
suspects, why Harrisons political significance has been overlooked.
Harrison was an undoubted radical, as Dr
Parry observes: he went further
than the radical Calvinists on certain decisive issues of
historical interpretation, particularly the kind of magistracy sanctioned
by the example of the True Church, and the relationship between
imperial rule and true religion epitomised in the behaviour of Constantine
[my emphasis] (p. 200). To go further than radical Calvinists was
indeed to go a long way and adopt a position that few monarchs would
be happy to support especially if, in Dr Parrys words, his
political position implicitly questioned the possibility of
any harmonious relationship between continuous worldly monarchy
and those who sought to foster true religion. Such a position
explicitly places sovereignty as the prerogative of the (godly)
people, not that of the monarch. It resembles the arguments of the
Scottish reformers such as John Knox, George Buchanan and David
Hume of Godscroft, who felt it was their right and duty to curb
and control their sovereign if he or she strayed from the straight
and narrow. The most influential Huguenot treatise, Vindiciae
Contra Tyrannos (1579), explicitly linked tyrannicide to
Scotland through its (false) colophon, when the anonymous author
claimed that the work had been published in Edinburgh (it was actually
published in Basle) by Stephanus Junius Brutus, the Celt. A clearer
link between the Protestant politics of early modern Scotland and
Roman republicanism would be hard to imagine, the key idea being
that opposition to the godless ruler resembled efforts to found
the republic. And both, of course, necessitated the defeat of Roman
tyranny. Buchanan, it might be worth noting, went further than anyone
in arguing that the tyrant could be overthrown by a godly private
citizen. Most monarchomachs argued that the designated magistrate
had such powers and rights but not someone who did not even hold
political office. Buchanan also felt that the Scots had made a cardinal
error when they made their monarchy hereditary rather than elective.
Harrison may have gone even further, because he believed that
Israel committed a grave sin in demanding a king (p. 217).
For Harrison, the key event was the elevation
of Saul to the monarchy. While other commentators saw this act providing
a Biblical justification of kingship often one without restraints
- Harrison concentrated on developing a pointed contrast between
Saul the king and Samuel the prophet. Harrison sought to contrast
the worldly ruler to the minatory prophet who enjoyed an intimate
relationship with God (p. 218), and who rejected tyranny.
Israel started to look more like gentile nations when her people
elected a king not ordained by God. In doing so Harrison came close
to arguing that all government that was not directly inspired by
God was evil and should be opposed (mirroring his position on the
things indifferent in church controversies), and that
Israels position as gods chosen nation resulted from
the actions of her prophets and not her kings. Even Goodman and
Ponet did not go so far as to suggest that monarchy itself might
be inherently evil. Dr Parry suggests that Harrisons thoughts
may well have been turned to the England he inhabited when he complained
of Israels elite defending ill-gotten "tenures"
through ungodly "policie". (p. 223)
Nevertheless, Harrison did not, unsurprisingly,
establish a clear plan of action in case his hopes of reform failed
to materialise. He did conclude that tyrants and ungodly monarchs
richly deserved whatever gruesome fate they brought upon themselves,
but he also argued that England could escape its nemesis by
accepting the preaching which would reconstruct the godly commonwealth
(pp. 252-3). Even so, Harrison seems to have regarded political
intervention as an onerous duty and his writings praise those prophets
who chose to leade a private life farre from the court than
to be nere the king and plaie the flattering hypocrite (p.
263).
A Protestant
Vision is not, of course, without some flaws. There are times
when Dr Parry relies too heavily on the past conditional beloved
by biographers (for example, Harrison must have been struck
by the great personal relevance of Pauls life (p. 5)),
passing off reasonable speculations as though they were established
fact. There are other times when obvious comparisons are neglected
in favour of more striking links, a case in point being the attempt
to place great emphasis on the relationship between Harrisons
discussion of the Two Churches and that of John Hooker (in Chapter
one). The analogy is not mistaken, but the passage reads as though
the author were desperately trying not to relate Harrison to the
much better-known figures, John Bale and John Foxe, whose writings
on the tradition of the Two Churches have been analysed in exhaustive
detail.
The major quibble I would have with the
book is really a compliment to a cautious and diligent historian.
There are times when Dr Parry seems to me to be rather too modest
in the claims he makes for Harrisons significance and the
radical nature of his work. Dr Parry opens his chapter on the political
vision of William Harrison by castigating his subject and making
an excuse for his apparent incoherence:
Despite his low opinion of princes in
general, Harrison had dutifully to suspend his disbelief about
Elizabeths commitment to further reformation. This tension
can be partly resolved by an examination of Harrisons
views about Englands relationship to the ideal godly commonwealth,
but an element of incoherence must always be allowed for in
his thought, since he belonged to that historical majority of
individuals whose less than rigorous thinking allowed them to
accept simultaneously a number of logically contradictory propositions.
(p. 244)
It would be interesting to know whether
Dr Parry would argue this case now. It has become an almost axiomatic
assumption that Elizabeth was distrusted and criticised by virtually
all of her articulate and intelligent subjects from the 1580s onwards.
John Guys edited collection, The
Reign of Elizabeth: Court and Culture in the Last Decade
(Cambridge University Press, in association with the Folger Shakespeare
Institute; Cambridge, 1995), which outlined the sharp division between
her successful early reign and the disastrous later one, has come
to be accepted as a current orthodoxy. It may be the case that William
Harrison was a more consistent thinker than Dr Parry has given him
credit for and that he was one of the many writers who did not really
place his faith in any monarch. If so, then further questions need
to be asked. How typical or isolated was Harrison? Dr Parry notes
that he was rather more excitable in his interpretations of events
than many of his fellow historians and that he envisaged momentous
happenings resulting from the most mundane happenings
(p. 121). It would be useful to know whether he stands out as an
oddity in this or belongs to a wider tradition of historical exegesis.
Dr Parry suggests that Harrison was eccentric in his
arguments and beliefs, and that he was unlike the humanists who
sought to advise princes rather than to require them to vacate
their thrones and reverently listen to the preachers of the Word
(p. 248). It may be the case that our conception of humanism and
its possible manifestations has changed considerably since 1987,
enabling a wider interpretation of its political spectrum as well
as a breaking-down of the rigid separation between humanist and
Protestant beliefs and practices.
And what of Harrisons politics examined
in a wider context? Should we be adopting a British approach to
the question of religious division and not just an English or European
one? Was Harrison yet another figure who was more critical of female
rule than he made clear? If so, did he want a strong male monarch
on the throne to enforce Gods will, or was he of a more republican
cast, wanting the people to control the prince? Some historians
cannot tolerate the r word and cry anachronism
if anyone uses it to describe words or events before 1640. But a
strong case can be made that George Buchanan, whose writings Harrison
would have known (even though he does not feature in Dr Parrys
book), was a republican because he used classical and Christian
examples to argue that the people should have control over the monarch
whose duty was to administer the laws that they had established
wisely and properly. Harrisons writings, so carefully and
intelligently outlined by Dr Parry, suggest that he made similar
connections, using his knowledge of Biblical history to argue that
the godly rather than the monarchy should control the tenor of English
life. Elsewhere Dr Parry argues that Harrisons eagerness
to find some evidence of godliness in Elizabeths actions also
reflects his reluctance to face the logical consequences of his
general assumptions about the problematical relationship between
worldly princes and true religion (p. 233). It is just as
likely that it was fear and caution that enforced this uneasy compromise,
as well as a pragmatic desire to play some part in inaugurating
the godly kingdom in an imperfect world. That Harrisons manuscript
writings contain much harsher criticisms of contemporary society
and its religious failures notably the self-aggrandising
behaviour of the nobility than his published works should
surely come as no surprise.
A Protestant
Vision is a fine work that makes important contributions
to intellectual, religious and political history. Indeed, its singular
achievement is to link these often disparate subjects together making
it impossible to study the Reformation in isolation from early modern
science or any debates on early modern political formations (to
give one example, Thomas Smith, in his De
Republica Anglorum, used Harrisons ideas alongside
discussions of classical political forms). It is now up to other
scholars to follow Dr Parrys lead and insights.
December 2002 |